Is the definition of sanity arbitrary or independent of societal opinions of what a person ought to be?
For example, if everyone alive barring you thought they had the spirit
of the Archangel Gabriel within them, what right would you have to call
yourself sane and others insane? The Soviets declared 'anti-Socialist'
behavior a mental disorder. What gives us the right to condemn the USSR
for such practices? What's the difference between the Soviet practice
and our usual practice of considering someone possessed of Gabriel
insane?
Also, is having any mental disorder enough to keep you from having sound
mind and will"? Also, what constitutes a sound mind and will, and what
criteria do you use to determine it?"
The wikipedia entry, IMO, is a fairly good starting point. Basically it
says that the scientific method can shed light of what is meant by
sanity independent of societal perceptions
From Wikipedia: Sanity
From Sanity (wikipedia entry)
A theory of sanity was proposed by Alfred Korzybski in his general
semantics. He believed that sanity was tied to the structural fit or
lack of it between our reactions to the world and what is actually going
on in the world. He expressed this notion in a map-territory analogy:
"A map is not the territory it represents, but, if correct, it has a
"similar structure" to the territory, which accounts for its
usefulness."[1] Given that science continually seeks to adjust its
theories structurally to fit the facts, i.e., adjusts its maps to fit
the territory, and thus advances more rapidly than any other field, he
believed that the key to understanding sanity would be found in the
study of the methods of science (and the study of structure as revealed
by science). The adoption of a scientific outlook and attitude of
continual adjustment by the individual toward his or her assumptions was
the way, so he claimed. In other words, there were "factors of sanity
to be found in the physico-mathematical methods of science."
Psychiatrist Philip S. Graven suggested the term "un-sane" to describe a
condition that is not exactly insane, but not quite sane either.[2]
In The Sane Society, published in 1955, psychologist Erich Fromm
proposed that, not just individuals, but entire societies "may be
lacking in sanity". Fromm argued that one of the most deceptive features
of social life involves "consensual validation."[3]:
“ It is naively assumed that the fact that the majority of people share
certain ideas or feelings proves the validity of these ideas and
feelings. Nothing is further from the truth... Just as there is a folie à
deux there is a folie à millions. The fact that millions of people
share the same vices does not make these vices virtues, the fact that
they share so many errors does not make the errors to be truths, and the
fact that millions of people share the same form of mental pathology
does not make these people sane.[4]
And then there's Michel Foucalt
Genre History (299 pp.)
Keywords Communication, Cross-Cultural Issues, Doctor-Patient
Relationship, Freedom, History of Medicine, History of Science,
Hospitalization, Hysteria, Institutionalization, Law and Medicine,
Literary Theory, Medical Advances, Mental Illness, Poverty, Power
Relations, Psychiatry, Psychotherapy, Public Health, Society
Summary
A severe synopsis of Foucault's first major work might show how Foucault
charts the journey of the mad from liberty and discourse to confinement
and silence and how this is signposted by the exercise of power. He
starts in the epoch when madness was an "undifferentiated experience"
(ix), a time when the mad roamed the countryside in "an easy wandering
existence" (8); Foucault shows the historical and cultural developments
that lead to "that other form of madness, by which men, in an act of
sovereign reason, confine their neighbors" (ix), challenging the
optimism of William Tuke and Phillipe Pinel's "liberation" of the mad
and problematizing the genesis of psychiatry, a "monologue of reason
about madness" (xi).
Central to this is the notion of confinement as a meaningful exercise.
Foucault's history explains how the mad came first to be confined; how
they became identified as confined due to moral and economic factors
that determined those who ought to be confined; how they became
perceived as dangerous through their confinement, partly by way of
atavistic identification with the lepers whose place they had come to
occupy; how they were "liberated" by Pinel and Tuke, but in their
liberation remained confined, both physically in asylums and in the
designation of being mad; and how this confinement subsequently became
enacted in the figure of the psychiatrist, whose practice is "a certain
moral tactic contemporary with the end of the eighteenth century,
preserved in the rites of the asylum life, and overlaid by the myths of
positivism." Science and medicine, notably, come in at the later stages,
as practices "elaborated once this division" between the mad and the
sane has been made (ix).
Commentary
This history is one of Foucault's most fascinating explorations of the
relationship between knowledge and power. It would be simplistic to say
that an exercise of power is then justified by a body of knowledge which
forgets how it is related to that exercise of power, but that is one
message that can be derived from Foucault's project here: the role of
discourses, imaginary figures, political and economic developments, all
play a role in organizing the relationships between people, power, and
knowledge.
Says Foucault: "the essential thing is that the enterprise did not
proceed from observation to the construction of explanatory images; that
on the contrary, the images assured the initial role of synthesis, that
their organizing force made possible a structure of perception, in
which at last the symptoms could attain their significant value and be
organized as the visible presence of truth" (135). This could be a
criticism of psychiatry, of science, or of Foucault's project itself.
The book provides a deeply challenging portrait of madness and, Foucault
argues, the loss of madness as a voice in dialogue with reason:
although many psychologists, psychiatrists and psychoanalysts may argue
that the analyst's couch (or chair, etc) has allowed this voice to
return, they might want to consider Foucault's provocative arguments to
the contrary, that the Freudian development of therapeutic listening
was, though a return of sorts to listening to madness, nevertheless
undertaken under such circumstances and in such a relationship that it
"can unravel some of the forms of madness [but] it remains a stranger to
the sovereign enterprise of unreason. It can neither liberate nor
transcribe, nor most certainly explain, what is essential in this
enterprise" (278).
As he will do in Birth of the Clinic, Foucault watches men describe
other men and women, and sees how their observations begin to take a
shape recognizable to us today: but this is not "because in the course
of centuries we have learned 'to open our eyes' to real symptoms; it is
not because we have purified our perception to the point of
transparency: it is because in the experience of madness, these concepts
were organized around certain qualitative themes that lent them their
unity, gave them their significant coherence, made them finally
perceptible" (130). This is a challenging book for psychologists,
psychiatrists, and other physicians, and is a gauntlet thrown that few
have chosen to take up.
Publisher Random House
Edition 1988 (Vintage)
Place Published New York
Miscellaneous First Published in the United States by Pantheon Books in
1965, and in France as Histoire de la Folie in 1961 by Librarie Plon
Maybe I’m misreading Foucalt, but it sounds like he’s asserting that
“sanity” is enforcement of societal and/or elite expectations of what a
person ought to be and/or assumptions of what “proper mental
health” is, then misusing the scientific method to define what sanity is
– namely by assuming the societal and/or elite definitions are the only
proper foundation on which to build, then building psychiatry’s whole
superstructure on that foundation.
From another angle, there seems to be both arbitrary and objective definitions of
sanity, which I find agreeable. In fact, sanity seems to be more of a legal term than a scientific one. Still, to repeat what I said earlier, I think
the scientific method of discerning the truth of a situation is a pretty
objective standard. What that means is that if a person uses the
scientific method to interpret the facts he or she comes across, and
they are independently confirmable, then that signals a sound mind.
Even within the scientific method, we still have to ask how many gross mistakes in perception and
interpretation they make. If you ask me, a good general rule is this: the more simple the fact
or relationship, the more a gross error in perception or judgment will
count towards insanity. For example, claiming you are, in fact, the
POTUS when you clearly are not definitely counts for insanity. If you
say you have a good chance to be POTUS when you clearly have little to
no chance of getting elected, then you may close to the edge. On the
other hand, if a highly ambitious politician thinks to him or herself "I
deserve to sit in the Oval Office because I'm more right than
POTUS is and therefore can administer the country better", we
probably won't consider the politician insane - although we'd consider
him or her an egotistical fool. However, the best litmus tests I can think of are:
(a) whether their cognitive processes and self-awareness of
who they are are strikingly out of touch with reality, and
(b) the degree
of emotional control or self-discipline they have in interpersonal
interactions (i.e. no consistent history of emotional reactions common
knowledge says are well outside the boundaries of legal behavior).
Of
these, I think (a) is more important, although no violations of (a) and
several violations of (b) are are at least fairly likely symptomatic of a
personality disorder (an entirely separate category from insanity).
Nevertheless, I find it difficult to disagree that one of society's eternal dangers concerning individual freedom and dignity concerns developing too broad or too narrow a definition of sanity - namely
"behavior highly outside the norm". Some definitions would cover some of
the greatest authors, writers, musicians, artists, etc. (although
greatness itself doesn't not immunize one from insanity).
In the end, the definition of sanity can't help but be at least partially arbitrary, especially for the qualitative traits (as opposed to quantitative ones). Even so, I think that any definition of sanity must start from how a person's mind processes objective (i.e. falsifiable and confirmable) facts and data about reality. Certainly this is more important
than the definition based on collective society's mere say-so.
No comments:
Post a Comment